Human Nature in Politics - Third Edition by Graham Wallas
page 41 of 260 (15%)
page 41 of 260 (15%)
|
common to the whole race, and increase in their importance with an
increase in the number of those influenced by them. It may be worth while, therefore, to attempt a description of some of the more obvious or more important political impulses, remembering always that in politics we are dealing not with such clear-cut separate instincts as we may find in children and animals, but with tendencies often weakened by the course of human evolution, still more often transferred to new uses, and acting not simply but in combination or counteraction. Aristotle, for instance, says that it is 'affection' (or 'friendship,' for the meaning of [Greek: philía] stands half way between the two words) which 'makes political union possible,' and 'which law-givers consider more important than justice.' It is, he says, a hereditary instinct among animals of the same race, and particularly among men.[6] If we look for this political affection in its simplest form, we see it in our impulse to feel 'kindly' towards any other human being of whose existence and personality we become vividly aware. This impulse can be checked and overlaid by others, but any one can test its existence and its prerationality in his own case by going, for instance, to the British Museum and watching the effect on his feelings of the discovery that a little Egyptian girl baby who died four thousand years ago rubbed the toes of her shoes by crawling upon the floor. [6] _Ethics_, Bk. viii. chap. I. [Greek: phýsei t' enypárchein éoike ... ou pónon en anthrôpois allà kaì en órnisi kaì tois pleístois tôn zôôn, kaì tois homoethnési pròs állêla, kaì málista tois anthrôpois ... éoike dè kaì tàs póleis synéchein hê philía, kaì hoi nomothétai mallon perì autên spoudázein ê tên dikaiosýnên]. |
|