Moral Principles and Medical Practice - The Basis of Medical Jurisprudence by Charles Coppens
page 45 of 155 (29%)
page 45 of 155 (29%)
![]() | ![]() |
|
course of his professional life. But if we had no Doctors, such a loss
would be a much greater evil to mankind than their occasional mistakes. Here then we seem to be in a dilemma, with evil on both sides of us. And then we are reminded of that other principle of which we spoke before, that we may never do evil at all that good may come of it. What shall we do? The solution is this: we should never _do_ evil, but we are often justified in _permitting_ evil to happen; in other words, we can never will evil _directly_, but we can often will it _indirectly_: we can do what is right in itself, even though we know or fear that evil will also result from our good act. This conduct requires four conditions: 1. That we do not wish the evil itself, but make all reasonable effort to avoid it. 2. That the immediate effect we wish to produce is good in itself. 3. That the good effect intended is at least as important as the evil effect permitted. 4. That the evil is not made a means used to obtain the good effect. Now let us apply these principles to the case in hand. 1. If the medicine is necessary to save the mother's life, and it is not certain to bring on abortion, though it is likely to do so, then the good effect is greater and more immediate or direct than the bad effect; then give the medicine to save the mother, and permit the probable death of the child. 2. If the medicine is not necessary to save the mother's life, though very useful, for the sake of such an advantage, you cannot justly expose the child's life to serious danger. 3. But if the danger it is exposed to is not serious but slight, and the |
|